女神电子书 > 浪漫言情电子书 > introduction to the metaphysic of morals >

第6部分

introduction to the metaphysic of morals-第6部分

小说: introduction to the metaphysic of morals 字数: 每页4000字

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!




  The simplicity of this law; in comparison with the great and

manifold consequences which may be drawn from it; as well as its

commanding authority and supremacy without the accompaniment of any

visible motive or sanction; must certainly at first appear very

surprising。 And we may well wonder at the power of our reason to

determine the activity of the will by the mere idea of the

qualification of a maxim for the universality of a practical law;

especially when we are taught thereby that this practical moral law

first reveals a property of the will which the speculative reason

would never have come upon either by principles a priori; or from

any experience whatever; and even if it had ascertained the fact; it

could never have theoretically established its possibility。 This

practical law; however; not only discovers the fact of that property

of the will; which is freedom; but irrefutably establishes it。 Hence

it will be less surprising to find that the moral laws are

undemonstrable; and yet apodeictic; like the mathematical

postulates; and that they; at the same time; open up before us a whole

field of practical knowledge; from which reason; on its theoretical

side; must find itself entirely excluded with its speculative idea

of freedom and all such ideas of the supersensible generally。

  The conformity of an action to the law of duty constitutes its

legality; the conformity of the maxim of the action with the law

constitutes its morality。 A maxim is thus a subjective principle of

action; which the individual makes a rule for himself as to how in

fact he will act。

  On the other hand; the principle of duty is what reason

absolutely; and therefore objectively and universally; lays down in

the form of a command to the individual; as to how he ought to act。

  The supreme principle of the science of morals accordingly is

this: 〃Act according to a maxim which can likewise be valid as a

universal law。〃 Every maxim which is not qualified according to this

condition is contrary to Morality。

  Laws arise from the will; viewed generally as practical reason;

maxims spring from the activity of the will in the process of

choice。 The latter in man is what constitutes free…will。 The will

which refers to nothing else than mere law can neither be called

free nor not free; because it does not relate to actions

immediately; but to the giving of a law for the maxim of actions; it

is therefore the practical reason itself。 Hence as a faculty; it is

absolutely necessary in itself; and is not subject to any external

necessitation。 It is; therefore; only the act of choice in the

voluntary process that can be called free。

  The freedom of the act of will; however; is not to be defined as a

liberty of indifference (libertas indifferentae); that; is; as a

capacity of choosing to act for or against the law。 The voluntary

process; indeed; viewed as a phenomenal appearance; gives many

examples of this choosing in experience; and some have accordingly

so defined the free…will。 For freedom; as it is first made knowable by

the moral law; is known only as a negative property in us; as

constituted by the fact of not being necessitated to act by sensible

principles of determination。 Regarded as a noumenal reality;

however; in reference to man as a pure rational intelligence; the

act of the will cannot be at all theoretically exhibited; nor can it

therefore be explained how this power can act necessitatingly in

relation to the sensible activity in the process of choice; or

consequently in what the positive quality of freedom consists。 Only

thus much we can see into and comprehend; that although man; as a

being belonging to the world of sense; exhibits… as experience

shows… a capacity of choosing not only conformably to the law but also

contrary to it; his freedom as a rational being belonging to the world

of intelligence cannot be defined by reference merely to sensible

appearances。 For sensible phenomena cannot make a super…sensible

object… such as free…will is… intelligible; nor can freedom ever be

placed in the mere fact that the rational subject can make a choice in

conflict with his own law…giving reason; although experience may prove

that it happens often enough; notwithstanding our inability to

conceive how it is possible。 For it is one thing to admit a

proposition as based on experience; and another thing to make it the

defining principle and the universal differentiating mark of the act

of free…will; in its distinction from the arbitrium brutum s。

servum; because the empirical proposition does not assert that any

particular characteristic necessarily belongs to the conception in

question; but this is requisite in the process of definition。

Freedom in relation to the internal legislation of reason can alone be

properly called a power; the possibility of diverging from the law

thus given is an incapacity or want of power。 How then can the

former be defined by the latter? It could only be by a definition

which would add to the practical conception of the free…will; its

exercise as shown by experience; but this would be a hybrid definition

which would exhibit the conception in a false light。

  A morally practical law is a proposition which contains a

categorical imperative or command。 He who commands by a law (imperans)

is the lawgiver or legislator。 He is the author of the obligation that

accompanies the law; but he is not always the author of the law

itself。 In the latter case; the law would be positive; contingent; and

arbitrary。 The law which is imposed upon us a priori and

unconditionally by our own reason may also be expressed as

proceeding from the will of a supreme lawgiver or the Divine will。

Such a will as supreme can consequently have only rights and not

duties; and it only indicates the idea of a moral being whose will

is law for all; without conceiving of him as the author of that will。

  Imputation; in the moral sense; is the judgement by which anyone

is declared to be the author or free cause of an action which is

then regarded as his moral fact or deed; and is subjected to law。 When

the judgement likewise lays down the juridical consequences of the

deed; it is judicial or valid (imputatio judiciaria s。 valida);

otherwise it would be only adjudicative or declaratory (imputatio

dijudicatoria)。 That person… individual or collective… who is invested

with the right to impute actions judicially; is called a judge or a

court (judex s。 forum)。

  When any one does; in conformity with duty; more than he can be

compelled to do by the law; it is said to be meritorious (meritum)。

What is done only in exact conformity with the law; is what is due

(debitum)。 And when less is done than can be demanded to be done by

the law; the result is moral demerit (demeritum) or culpability。

  The juridical effect or consequence of a culpable act of demerit

is punishment (paena); that of a meritorious act is reward (praemium);

assuming that this reward was promised in the law and that it formed

the motive of the action。 The coincidence or exact conformity of

conduct to what is due has no juridical effect。 Benevolent

remuneration (remuneratio s。 repensio benefica) has no place in

juridical relations。

  The good or bad consequences arising from the performance of an

obligated action… as also the consequences arising from failing to

perform a meritorious action… cannot be imputed to the agent (modus

imputation is tollens)。 The good consequences of a meritorious action…

as also the bad consequences of a wrongful action… may be imputed to

the agent (modus imputation is poneus)。

  The degree of the imputability of actions is to be reckoned

according to the magnitude of the hindrances or obstacles which it has

been necessary for them to overcome。 The greater the natural

hindrances in the sphere of sense; and the less the moral hindrance of

duty; so much the more is a good deed imputed as meritorious。 This may

be seen by considering such examples as rescuing a man who is an

entire stranger from great distress; and at very considerable

sacrifice。 Conversely; the less the natural hindrance; and the greater

the hindrance on the ground of duty; so much the more is a

transgression imputable as culpable。 Hence the state of mind of the

agent or doer of a deed makes a difference in imputing its

consequences; according as he did it in passion or performed it with

coolness and deliberation。





                              …THE END…


返回目录 上一页 回到顶部 0 0

你可能喜欢的